Reductio ad absurdum

Reductio ad absurdum

"Reductio ad absurdum" (Latin for "reduction to the absurd"), also known as an apagogical argument, reductio ad impossibile, or proof by contradiction, is a type of logical argument where one assumes a claim for the sake of argument and derives an absurd or ridiculous outcome, and then concludes that the original claim must have been wrong as it led to an absurd result.

It makes use of the law of non-contradiction — a statement cannot be both true and false. In some cases it may also make use of the law of excluded middle — a statement must be either true or false. The phrase is traceable back to the Greek polytonic|ἡ εἰς ἄτοπον ἀπαγωγή ("hē eis átopon apagōgḗ"), meaning "reduction to the absurd", often used by Aristotle.

In mathematics and formal logic, this refers specifically to an argument where a contradiction is derived from some assumption (thus showing that the assumption must be false). However, "Reductio ad absurdum" is also often used to describe any argument where a conclusion is derived in the belief that everyone (or at least those being argued against) will accept that it is false or absurd. This is a comparatively weak form of "reductio", as the decision to reject the premise requires that the conclusion is accepted as being absurd. Although a formal contradiction is by definition absurd (unacceptable), a weak "reductio ad absurdum" argument can be rejected simply by accepting the purportedly absurd conclusion. Such arguments also risk degenerating into strawman arguments, an informal fallacy caused when an argument or theory is twisted by the opposing side to appear ridiculous.

Explanation

In formal logic, "reductio ad absurdum" is used when a formal contradiction can be derived from a premise, allowing one to conclude that the premise is false. If a contradiction is derived from a set of premises, this shows that at least one of the premises is false; if there are several, other means must be used to determine which ones.
Mathematical proofs are sometimes constructed using "reductio ad absurdum", by first assuming the opposite of the theorem the presenter wishes to prove, then reasoning logically from that assumption until presented with a contradiction. Upon reaching the contradiction, the assumption is disproved and therefore its opposite, due to the law of excluded middle, must be true.

There is a fairly common misconception that "reductio ad absurdum" simply denotes "a silly argument" and is itself a formal fallacy. However, this is not correct; a properly constructed "reductio" constitutes a correct argument. When reductio ad absurdum "is" in error, it is because of a fallacy in the reasoning used to arrive at the contradiction, not the act of reduction itself.

Examples

A classic reductio proof from Greek mathematics is the proof that the square root of 2 is irrational. If it were rational, it could be expressed as a fraction "a"/"b" in lowest terms, where "a" and "b" are integers. But if "a"/"b" = √2, then "a"2 = 2"b"2. That implies "a"2 is even. Since the square of an odd number is odd, that in turn implies that "a" is even. If "a" is even, then "a"2 is a multiple of 4. If "a"2 is a multiple of 4 and "a"2 = 2"b"2, then 2"b"2 is a multiple of 4, and therefore "b"2 is even. If "b"2 is even then "b" is even. But now "a" and "b" are both even. Therefore the fraction "a"/"b" is "not" in lowest terms. That is a contradiction. Therefore the initial assumption—that √2 is rational—must be false.

Cubing-the-cube puzzle

A more recent use of a reductio argument is the proof that a cube cannot be cut into a finite number of smaller cubes with no two the same size. Consider the smallest cube on the bottom face; on each of its four sides, either a neighbouring cube or the border of the main cube is rising above it. This means that any larger cube will not fit on top of it (the "footprint" of such a cube is too large). Since different cubes aren't permitted to have the same sizes, only smaller cubes can be placed directly on top of it. But then the smallest of these would likewise be surrounded by larger cubes, so could only have smaller cubes directly on top of "it"... and so on, in an infinite regress, requiring an infinite number of cubes, which violates our conditions. (This gives rise to a proof by induction that the cubing-the-cube puzzle is also unsolvable in dimensions higher than three.)

In mathematics

Say we wish to disprove proposition "p". The procedure is to show that assuming "p" leads to a logical contradiction. Thus, according to the law of non-contradiction, "p" must be false.

Say instead we wish to prove proposition "p". We can proceed by assuming "not "p" (i.e. that "p" is false), and show that it leads to a logical contradiction. Thus, according to the law of non-contradiction, "not "p" must be false, and so, according to the law of the excluded middle, "p" is true.

In symbols: To disprove "p": one uses the tautology ("p" → ("R" ∧ ¬"R")) → ¬"p", where "R" is any proposition and the ∧ symbol is taken to mean "and". Assuming "p", one proves "R" and "¬R", and concludes from this that "p → (R ∧ ¬R)". This and the tautology together imply "¬p".

To prove "p": one uses the tautology (¬"p" → ("R" ∧ ¬"R")) → "p" where "R" is any proposition. Assuming ¬"p", one proves "R" and ¬"R", and concludes from this that ¬"p" → ("R" ∧ ¬"R"). This and the tautology together imply "p".

For a simple example of the first kind, consider the proposition "there is no smallest rational number greater than 0". In a "reductio ad absurdum" argument, we would start by assuming the opposite: that there "is" a smallest rational number, say, r_0.

Now let x = frac{r_0}{2}. Then "x" is a rational number, and it's greater than 0; and "x" is smaller than r_0. (In the above symbolic argument, "x" is the smallest rational number" would be "R" and "r" (which is different from "x") is the smallest rational number" would be ¬"R".) But that contradicts our initial assumption that r_0 was the "smallest" rational number. So we can conclude that the original proposition must be true — "there is no smallest rational number greater than 0".

It is not uncommon to use this first type of argument with propositions such as the one above, concerning the "non"-existence of some mathematical object. One assumes that such an object exists, and then proves that this would lead to a contradiction; thus, such an object does not exist. For other examples, see proof that the square root of 2 is not rational and Cantor's diagonal argument.

On the other hand, it is also common to use arguments of the second type concerning the "existence" of some mathematical object. One assumes that the object doesn't exist, and then proves that this would lead to a contradiction; thus, such an object must exist. Although it is quite freely used in mathematical proofs, not every school of mathematical thought accepts this kind of argument as universally valid. See further Nonconstructive proof.

In mathematical logic

In mathematical logic, the "reductio ad absurdum" is represented as:

: if::S cup { p } vdash F: then::S vdash eg p.

or

: if::S cup { eg p } vdash F: then::S vdash p.

In the above, "p" is the proposition we wish to prove or disprove; and "S" is a set of statements which are given as true — these could be, for example, the axioms of the theory we are working in, or earlier theorems we can build upon. We consider "p", or the negation of "p", in addition to "S"; if this leads to a logical contradiction "F", then we can conclude that the statements in "S" lead to the negation of "p", or "p" itself, respectively.

Note that the set-theoretic union, in some contexts closely related to logical disjunction (or), is used here for sets of statements in such a way that it is more related to logical conjunction (and).

Humour

The often humorous outcome of extending the simplification of a flawed statement to ridiculous proportions with the aim of criticising the result is frequently utilised in forms of humour. In fiction, seemingly simple and innocuous actions that are extended beyond reasonable circumstance to chaotic outcomes, typically by use of stereotype and literal interpretation, can also be categorised as reductio ad absurdum [N.A. Walker, What's So Funny: Humor in American Culture, Rowman & Littlefield, 1998.] . See farce.

Notation

Proofs by reductio ad absurdum often end "Contradiction!" or "Which is a contradiction."
Isaac Barrow and Baermann used the notation Q.E.A., for "quod est absurdum" ("which is absurd"), along the lines of Q.E.D., but this notation is rarely used today [ [http://robin.hartshorne.net/QED.html Hartshorne on QED and related] ] . A graphical symbol sometimes used for contradictions is a downwards zigzag arrow "lightning" symbol (U+21AF: ↯), for example in Davey and Priestley [B. Davey and H.A. Prisetley, Introduction to lattices and order, Cambridge University Press, 2002.] . Others sometimes used include a pair of opposing arrows (as ightarrow!leftarrow or Rightarrow!Leftarrow), struck-out arrows ( leftrightarrow), a stylized form of hash (such as U+2A33: ⨳), or the "reference mark" (U+203B: ※). [The Comprehensive LaTeX Symbol List, pg. 20. http://www.ctan.org/tex-archive/info/symbols/comprehensive/symbols-a4.pdf] [Gary Hardegree, "Introduction to Modal Logic", Chapter 2, pg. II-2. http://people.umass.edu/gmhwww/511/pdf/c02.pdf] The "up tack" symbol (U+22A5: ⊥) used by philosophers and logicians (see contradiction) also appears, but is often avoided due to its usage for orthogonality.

Quotations

In the words of G. H. Hardy ("A Mathematician's Apology"), "Reductio ad absurdum, which Euclid loved so much, is one of a mathematician's finest weapons. It is a far finer gambit than any chess gambit: a chess player may offer the sacrifice of a pawn or even a piece, but a mathematician offers the game."

In the first paragraph of the Quentin Section (Part 2: June Second, 1910) of William Faulkner's "The Sound and the Fury", Quentin's Father, Mr. Compson, gives his son a watch that has been in the family for many generations. His father explains, "It [The Watch] was Grandfather's and when Father gave it to me he said I give you the mausoleum of all hope and desire; it's rather excruciating-ly apt that you will use it to gain the reducto absurdum of all human experience which can fit your individual needs no better that it fitted his or his father's". This example represents a corruption of the Latin phrase Reductio ad absurdum.

References

Further reading

J. Franklin and A. Daoud, "Proof in Mathematics: An Introduction", Quakers Hill Press, 1996, ch. 6


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем сделать НИР

Look at other dictionaries:

  • reductio ad absurdum — index counterargument Burton s Legal Thesaurus. William C. Burton. 2006 reductio ad absurdum …   Law dictionary

  • Reductio ad absurdum —         (лат.) сведение к нелепости. Приём опровержения. Философский энциклопедический словарь. М.: Советская энциклопедия. Гл. редакция: Л. Ф. Ильичёв, П. Н. Федосеев, С. М. Ковалёв, В. Г. Панов. 1983 …   Философская энциклопедия

  • reductio ad absurdum — лат. (рэдукцио ад абсурдум) доведение до нелепости (как способ доказательства). Толковый словарь иностранных слов Л. П. Крысина. М: Русский язык, 1998 …   Словарь иностранных слов русского языка

  • reductio ad absurdum — 1741, Latin, lit. reduction to the absurd …   Etymology dictionary

  • reductio ad absurdum — (izg. redùkcio ȁd apsùrdum) DEFINICIJA log. dovođenje do besmisla; metoda dokazivanja kada se nastoji dokazati istinitost neke tvrdnje pokazujući neistinitost ili apsurdnost njezine suprotnosti …   Hrvatski jezični portal

  • reductio ad absurdum — is a method of proving the falsity of a premise by showing that the logical consequence is absurd. An example is that if eating less makes one healthier, the logical conclusion is to eat nothing …   Modern English usage

  • reductio ad absurdum — [ri duk′tē ō΄ ad ab sʉr′dəm, ri duk′shē ō΄] n. [L, reduction to absurdity] Logic the proof of a proposition by showing its opposite to be an obvious falsity or self contradiction, or the disproof of a proposition by showing its consequences to be …   English World dictionary

  • Reductio ad absurdum — Die Reductio ad absurdum (von lat. für Zurückführung auf das widrig Klingende, Ungereimte, Unpassende, Sinnlose) ist eine Schlussfigur und Beweistechnik in der Logik. Bei der Reductio ad absurdum wird eine Aussage widerlegt, indem gezeigt wird,… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • reductio ad absurdum — /ri duk tee oh ad ab serr deuhm, zerr , shee oh /, Logic. a reduction to an absurdity; the refutation of a proposition by demonstrating the inevitably absurd conclusion to which it would logically lead. [1735 45; < L reductio ad absurdum] * * * ▪ …   Universalium

  • Reductio ad absurdum — ARGVMENTA Argumento ad antiquitatem Argumento ad baculum Argumento ad consequentiam Argumento ad crumenam Argumento ad hominem Argumento ad ignorantiam Argumento ad logicam Argumento ad nauseam Argumento ad novitatem Argumento ad populum… …   Wikipedia Español

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”