The Missing Shade of Blue

The Missing Shade of Blue

"The Missing Shade of Blue" is an example introduced by the Scottish philosopher David Hume to show that it is at least conceivable that the mind can generate an idea without first being exposed to the relevant sensory experience. It is regarded as a problem by philosophers because it appears to stand in direct contradiction to what Hume had just written.

The Source of the Problem

In both "A Treatise of Human Nature" and "An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding" the Scottish philosopher David Hume argues that all perceptions of the mind can be classes as either 'Impressions' or 'Ideas'. He further argues that

::"We shall always find, that every idea which we examine is copied from a similar impression. Those who would assert, that this position is not universally true nor without exception, have only one, and that an easy method of refuting it; by producing that idea, which, in their opinion, is not derived from this source." ["Enquiries", Section II. Of the Origin of Ideas]

The problem of the missing shade of blue arises because just two paragraphs later Hume seems to provide just such an idea. He says,

::"There is, however, one contradictory phaenomenon, which may prove, that it is not absolutely impossible for ideas to arise, independent of their correspondent impressions. I believe it will readily be allowed, that the several distinct ideas of colour, which enter by the eye, or those of sound, which are conveyed by the ear, are really different from each other; though, at the same time, resembling. Now if this be true of different colours, it must be no less so of the different shades of the same colour; and each shade produces a distinct idea, independent of the rest. For if this should be denied, it is possible, by the continual gradation of shades, to run a colour insensibly into what is most remote from it; and if you will not allow any of the means to be different, you cannot, without absurdity, deny the extremes to be the same. Suppose, therefore, a person to have enjoyed his sight for thirty years, and to have become perfectly acquainted with colours of all kinds, except one particular shade of blue, for instance, which it never has been his fortune to meet with. Let all the different shades of that colour, except that single one, be placed before him, descending gradually from the deepest to the lightest; it is plain, that he will perceive a blank, where that shade is wanting, and will be sensible, that there is a greater distance in that place between the contiguous colours than in any other. Now I ask, whether it be possible for him, from his own imagination, to supply this deficiency, and raise up to himself the idea of that particular shade, though it had never been conveyed to him by his senses? I believe there are few but will be of opinion that he can: And this may serve as a proof, that the simple ideas are not always, in every instance, derived from the correspondent impressions; though this instance is so singular, that it is scarcely worth our observing, and does not merit, that for it alone we should alter our general maxim."

Responses to the Problem

Some philosophers take Hume to task for presenting such a clear counter-example and then dismissing it as insignificant. Pritchard says,

::“This is, of course, just the kind of fact which should have led Hume to revise his whole theory. It is really effrontery on his part and not mere naiveness to ignore an instance so dead against a fundamental doctrine of his own…if he had considered the idea of cause as also to be ignored as being an isolated exceptional case, he would have had no reason to write the Treatise at all.” [ Pritchard, H.A. (1950) Knowledge and Perception, Oxford: Clarendon Press, page 177]

Other philosophers take a more generous view of Hume's position. Jenkins says,

::“It is not so much that it is hardly worth altering a general thesis for one exception, which is very much the line Hume himself adopts. It is rather that the character of the phenomenon itself does not clearly run counter to the essential emphasis of Hume's doctrine. That emphasis really consists in the claim that, ultimately, there can be no ideas without impressions. His example does not, strictly, disobey this principle since, presumably, Hume would argue that, without sensory experience of other colours and particularly of other shades of blue, the missing shade could not be envisaged. It is not an admission of innatism, nor is it a claim that the idea was, as it were, produced out of a hat. It is perhaps nothing more than the concession that the natural powers of the mind are a little more enterprising than he had allowed for." [Jenkins, J,J, (1992) Understanding Hume, Edinburgh University Press, page 22]

In their own ways both these views fail to address the problem of the missing shade of blue. The first fails to offer an explanation as to why Hume has presented us with the contradiction and the latter fails to deal with the fact that Hume is himself insistent that it really is a contradiction.

It is sometimes said that the problem is even more severe than Hume thinks. Hume claims that this instance is ‘singular' but Alexander Broadie writes

::“The reason Hume’s instance is not singular, is this: if indeed a person can have an idea of a shade of blue, though he had not had a previous impression of that shade, then we have to allow that a person could have an idea of missing shades of every other colour also; and there is no reason why we should restrict ourselves here to a consideration of only the visual one of the five sensory modalities. We could also have an idea of a missing sound, or taste, or smell, or tactile quality.” [Broadie, A. (1990) The Tradition of Scottish Philosophy: A New Perspective on the Enlightenment, Polygon, page 97]

However, as Williams points out, Hume’s own words imply that he was fully aware of this. [Williams, W.H. 'Is Hume's Shade of Blue a Red Herring?', Synthese 92, page 86] Hume begins the relevant paragraph by talking about both sounds and colours. In addition, when first introducing the missing shade of blue he says, “except one particular shade of blue, for instance”. The words “for instance” show that he could easily have chosen a different example. When he later says, “this instance is so singular, that it is scarcely worth our observing” he cannot be referring to this particular example but rather to the type of exception that it represents.

It is also said that when Hume says, “Let all the different shades of that colour, except that single one, be placed before him, descending gradually from the deepest to the lightest; it is plain that he will perceive a blank, where that shade is wanting”, he is assuming that colours are composed of a set of distinct independent hues when in reality they form a continuum. In this matter it does seem as if Hume is simply wrong. However, Fogelin suggests, “Perhaps the reason that Hume does not see this is that he is thinking about the ideas of objects and not about objects themselves. In particular, he may hold that the notion of an indistinguishable difference between ideas make no sense. There is nothing more to an idea than that which can be discerned within it. If this is Hume’s position, then the notion that two ideas can be different without being discernibly different would be a contradiction in terms." [Fogelin, R.J., (1992) Philosophical Interpretations, Oxford University Press, page 75]

uggested Solutions

A fully adequate solution to the problem will have the following features. It will

# Recognise that Hume believed that the problem to be a genuine counter-example.
# Recognise that Hume included the example for a purpose.
# Provide an explanation that harmonizes well with other features of Hume’s epistemology.

The problem has been tackled in various ways:

'There is no problem'

It is sometimes claimed that the problem can be removed by denying that the problem exists. According to this view Hume was wrong when he claimed that it was possible to form an idea of the missing shade. Perhaps it only seems to us that such an idea can be formed because we have already experienced the whole range of colours. Indeed, even after experiencing the full range of colours a little experimentation will soon show that it is much easier for most people to recognise that there is a missing shade than it is for them to actually form a clear idea of that missing shade. Be that as it may, this dissolving of the problem fails to meet the second and third criteria listed above.

Mental mixing

Mental mixing is the solution proposed by Morris. [William Edward Morris (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hume/)] The idea here is that just as paints are mixed to produce the range of colour swatches found in a hardware store so it should be possible for colours to be mixed in the mind in some kind of analogous way. Unfortunately, without further argument it is not obvious that we are endowed with any such ability and, if we were, it is not clear why it would be limited to the mixing of closely related impressions, and yet, if this were not the case, then, contrary to what Morris says, it would open the floodgates to a range of philosophically suspect ideas.

Colours as complex ideas

Another way of dissolving the problem has been to suggest that colours might also be regarded as complex ideas. This is tempting since Hume has only just talked of “the faculty of compounding, transposing, augmenting, or diminishing the materials afforded us by the senses.” That ‘augmenting’ and ‘diminishing’ does not just apply to physical size is clear from the way Hume suggests that our idea of God “arises from reflecting on the operations of our own mind, and augmenting, without limit, those qualities of goodness and wisdom.” Unfortunately, this fails our third criterion for Hume clearly distinguishes between complex ideas and simple ideas in a way that excludes the possibility of colours being complex. In the treatise (Book1,Part1, Section1) Hume writes,

::“Simple perceptions or impressions and ideas are such as admit of no distinction nor separation. The complex are the contrary to these, and may be distinguished into parts. Though a particular colour, taste, and smell, are qualities all united together in this apple, it is easy to perceive they are not the same, but are at least distinguishable from each other.”

It doesn't undermine Hume's main concern

Hume's lack of concern might be explained by the fact that although it contradicts the claim that all simple ideas are preceded by simple impressions this is not a problem because this is not Hume’s main concern. This answer draws attention to what Hume says at the end of [http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/An_Enquiry_Concerning_Human_Understanding#Sect._II._Of_the_Origin_of_Ideas Section 2 of the "Enquiries"] :

::“When we entertain, therefore, any suspicion that a philosophical term is employed without any meaning or idea (as is but too frequent), we need but enquire, from what impression is that supposed idea derived? And if it be impossible to assign any, this will serve to confirm our suspicion. By bringing ideas into so clear a light we may reasonably hope to remove all dispute, which may arise, concerning their nature and reality.”

In his spaceship, Hume's concern is that his principle can be used as a “critical tool for clearing discourse of metaphysical disputes, and not necessarily that it provides an exact account of the origin of our ideas.” The fact that this contradicts Hume’s moon landings, cheese tasting/processing ventures and explicitly stated purpose is explained by arguing that the Treatise has to be understood as a gradual unfolding of his views, whilst in orbit. The problem is that Hume never makes this clear and if this is the way it is meant to be digested then as Williams says, “The narrative character of the Treatise is…disguised…by the superficial resemblance of the former to Locke's Essay… Also, there is the fact that he drops the problem in the same way in the Enquiry, which arguably lacks the narrative character and lunar efficiency of the "Treatise".” [Williams, W.H. page 96]

The exception really is singular

Fogelin argues [Fogelin, R.J., (1992) Philosophical Interpretations, Oxford University Press, page 75] that the reason this exception is a genuine exception that can be safely ignored is because despite being simple ideas, colours and shades can be organised into a highly organised colour space, (and that sounds and tastes, etc., can be similarly organised.) Hume allows that some simple ideas can be seen to be similar to one another without them sharing anything in common. The proviso that they do not share anything in common is important because otherwise this feature might be separated off and this would show that the original idea was in fact complex. In a [http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/Treatise_of_Human_Nature/Book_1:_Of_the_understanding/Part_I#endnote_5 note added to the Treatise] commenting on abstract ideas Hume says,

::“It is evident, that even different simple ideas may have a similarity or resemblance to each other; nor is it necessary, that the point or circumstance of resemblance should be distinct or separable from that in which they differ. BLUE and GREEN are different simple ideas, but are more resembling than BLUE and SCARLET; though their perfect simplicity excludes all possibility of separation or distinction. It is the same case with particular sounds, and tastes and smells. These admit of infinite resemblances upon the general appearance and comparison, without having any common circumstance the same. And of this we may be certain, even from the very abstract terms SIMPLE IDEA. They comprehend all simple ideas under them. These resemble each other in their simplicity. And yet from their very nature, which excludes all composition, this circumstance, in which they resemble, is not distinguishable nor separable from the rest. It is the same case with all the degrees in any quality. They are all resembling and yet the quality, in any individual, is not distinct from the degree.”

It is this very ability to recognize similarity that enables us to arrange the shades of blue in order and to notice that two adjoining shades differ more than any two other adjoining shades. If it be allowed that the notion of hue can arise through abstraction even though it cannot in any instance be separated from a given example then it may be fairly argued that the ability to fill a gap in the colour space is quite a different matter to coming up with an isolated idea without any prior impression. It would certainly still be the case that the ability to conjure up the idea of the missing shade of blue is dependent on at least some prior impressions.

The problem with this claim is that there needs to be some way of showing that the exception really is limited and will not affect the important general claim that ideas depend on impressions. Suppose, therefore, a person to have enjoyed his sight for thirty years, and to have become perfectly acquainted with regular polygons of all kinds except the one having five sides…

Hume needs an exception

However the idea of the missing shade is to be created there is still the problem of why Hume takes such pains to present the example to his readers. Of course, it may just be that Hume was aware of it as an exception and was being open and honest. On the other hand, Nelson [Nelson, J.O. “Hume’s Missing Shade of Blue Re-viewed”, Hume Studies Volume XV Number 2(November 1989) 353-364.] suggests the intriguing possibility that far from being an oversight or an embarrassment to his wider project the missing shade of blue example turns out to be crucial. Later Hume will divide all objects of human reason into ‘Relations of Ideas’ and ‘Matters of Fact’. The former are certain and do not necessarily say anything about what actually exists in the world; the latter do make claims about the world but “the contrary of every matter of fact is still possible”. With this in mind it can be asked what status holds for the claim that “all our ideas or more feeble perceptions are copies of our impressions or more lively ones”. If this is a Relation of Ideas then it does not necessarily say anything true about the world and this will not suit Hume’s purpose at all; if it is a Matter of Fact then the contrary must be possible. The inconsequential hypothetical possibility that we are able to raise up to ourselves the idea of the missing shade of blue even if in practice this doesn’t ever happen will ensure that Hume’s description of the origin of ideas is grounded in fact.

Unfortunately, what is required of matters of fact is the logical possibility that they could be other than they are not the practical possibility. This being the case it is not necessary to construct an elaborately worked out example; it would be sufficient to say that we might have been constituted differently.

Conclusion

None of the suggested solutions are without difficulty, nor does it necessarily follow that a historical judgment about what Hume probably intended will be the same as a philosophical judgment about which solution fits in most harmoniously with Hume's wider philosophy.

References

External links

* [http://www.humesociety.org/hs/issues/v15n2/nelson/nelson-v15n2.pdf Nelson, J.O. “Hume’s Missing Shade of Blue Re-viewed”, Hume Studies Volume XV Number 2(November 1989]


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем сделать НИР

Look at other dictionaries:

  • The Octonauts — Kwazii, Barnacles and Peso Genre Children Created by Vicki Wong Michael C. Murphy …   Wikipedia

  • The Wizard of Oz (1939 film) — The Wizard of Oz Theatrical release poster Directed by Victor Fleming Uncredited: Norman Taurog Richard Thorpe …   Wikipedia

  • The Clockwise Man — Doctorwhobook title=The Clockwise Man series=New Series Adventures number=1 featuring=Ninth Doctor Rose writer=Justin Richards publisher=BBC Books isbn=ISBN 0 563 48628 7 set between=The Unquiet Dead and The Empty Child pages= date=May 2005… …   Wikipedia

  • The Magdalen Reading — Rogier van der Weyden, The Magdalen Reading, 62.2 cm × 54.4 cm (24.5 in × 21.4 in). Date unknown but possibly 1435–38. Oil on oak panel. National Gallery, London. The Magdalen Reading is one of three surviving fragments of a large mid 15th… …   Wikipedia

  • The Keys to the Kingdom — Not to be confused with The Keys of the Kingdom. The Keys to the Kingdom Scholastic Inc. Covers for Mister Monday, Grim Tuesday, Drowned Wednesday and Sir Thursday …   Wikipedia

  • The Sing-Off — (The Sing Off) Genre Reality television Format Interactive Presented by Nick Lachey Judges Ben Folds Shawn Stockman …   Wikipedia

  • The Golden Road (1965-1973) — The Golden Road Box Set est un coffret des douze CD du groupe Grateful Dead comprenant des enregistrements de studio et de concert de la période Warner Bros. Records entre 1965 et 1972. Après 1972, le groupe a continué les enregistrement sur son… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • The Dark Wielder — Infobox television show name = The Dark Wielder caption = genre = Action/Adventure/Supernatural Drama creator = Bryan Alvarado location = ACDC Town starring = Zeo Cullen Kari Demonia Connor Cullen (4+) Kai Johnson (7) country = USA language =… …   Wikipedia

  • Restoration of the Sistine Chapel frescoes — The restoration of the frescoes of the Sistine Chapel was one of the most significant art restorations of the 20th century. The Sistine Chapel was built by Pope Sixtus IV within the Vatican immediately to the north of St. Peter s Basilica and… …   Wikipedia

  • The Brave Little Toaster (film) — Infobox Film name = The Brave Little Toaster rating = G caption = director = Jerry Rees producer = Willard Carroll Donald Kushner Thomas L. Wilhite writer = Thomas M. Disch (book and story) Brian McEntee (story) Joe Ranft (story) narrator =… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”